Efficient Envy-free Division
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Efficiency and fairness are two major goals of
welfare economics Welfare economics is a branch of economics that uses microeconomic techniques to evaluate well-being (welfare) at the aggregate (economy-wide) level. Attempting to apply the principles of welfare economics gives rise to the field of public ec ...
. Given a set of resources and a set of agents, the goal is to divide the resources among the agents in a way that is both
Pareto efficient Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality is a situation where no action or allocation is available that makes one individual better off without making another worse off. The concept is named after Vilfredo Pareto (1848–1923), Italian civil engin ...
(PE) and
envy-free Envy-freeness, also known as no-envy, is a criterion for fair division. It says that, when resources are allocated among people with equal rights, each person should receive a share that is, in their eyes, at least as good as the share received by a ...
(EF). The goal was first defined by
David Schmeidler David Schmeidler (1939 – 17 March 2022) was an Israeli mathematician and economic theorist. He was a Professor Emeritus at Tel Aviv University and the Ohio State University. Biography David Schmeidler was born in 1939 in Kraków, Poland. He ...
and
Menahem Yaari use both this parameter and , birth_date to display the person's date of birth, date of death, and age at death) --> , death_place = , death_cause = , body_discovered = , resting_place = , resting_place_coordinates = ...
. Later, the existence of such allocations has been proved under various conditions.


Existence of PEEF allocations

We assume that each agent has a preference-relation on the set of all bundles of commodities. The preferences are complete, transitive, and closed. Equivalently, each preference relation can be represented by a continuous utility function.


Weakly-convex preferences

''Theorem 1 (Varian):'' ''If the preferences of all agents are
convex Convex or convexity may refer to: Science and technology * Convex lens, in optics Mathematics * Convex set, containing the whole line segment that joins points ** Convex polygon, a polygon which encloses a convex set of points ** Convex polytop ...
and strongly
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
, then PEEF allocations exist.'' ''Proof'': The proof relies on the existence of a
competitive equilibrium Competitive equilibrium (also called: Walrasian equilibrium) is a concept of economic equilibrium introduced by Kenneth Arrow and Gérard Debreu in 1951 appropriate for the analysis of commodity markets with flexible prices and many traders, and se ...
with equal incomes. Assume that all resources in an economy are divided equally between the agents. I.e, if the total endowment of the economy is E, then each agent i\in 1,\dots,n: receives an initial endowment E_i = E/n. Since the preferences are ''convex'', the
Arrow–Debreu model In mathematical economics, the Arrow–Debreu model suggests that under certain economic assumptions (convex preferences, perfect competition, and demand independence) there must be a set of prices such that aggregate supplies will equal aggregat ...
implies that a competitive equilibrium exists. I.e, there is a price vector P and a partition X such that: * (CE) All agents maximize their utilities given their budget. I.e, if P\cdot Y \leq P\cdot X_i then Y \preceq_i X_i. * (EI) All agents have the same income in the equilibrium prices: for all i,j: P\cdot X_i = P\cdot X_j. Such an allocation is always EF. Proof: by the (EI) condition, for every i,j: P\cdot X_j \leq P\cdot X_i. Hence, by the (CE) condition, X_j \preceq_i X_i. Since the preferences are ''
monotonic In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of ord ...
'', any such allocation is also PE, since monotonicity implies
local nonsatiation In microeconomics, the property of local nonsatiation of consumer preferences states that for any bundle of goods there is always another bundle of goods arbitrarily close that is strictly preferred to it.''Microeconomic Theory'', by A. Mas-Colel ...
. See
fundamental theorems of welfare economics There are two fundamental theorems of welfare economics. The first states that in economic equilibrium, a set of complete markets, with complete information, and in perfect competition, will be Pareto optimal (in the sense that no further exchang ...
.


Examples

All examples involve an economy with two
goods In economics, goods are items that satisfy human wants and provide utility, for example, to a consumer making a purchase of a satisfying product. A common distinction is made between goods which are transferable, and services, which are not t ...
, x and y, and two agents, Alice and Bob. In all examples, the utilities are weakly-convex and continuous. A. Many PEEF allocations: The total endowment is (4,4). Alice and Bob have
linear utilities In economics and consumer theory, a linear utility function is a function of the form: ::u(x_1,x_2,\dots,x_m) = w_1 x_1 + w_2 x_2 + \dots w_m x_m or, in vector form: ::u(\overrightarrow) = \overrightarrow \cdot \overrightarrow where: * m is the n ...
, representing substitute goods: :u_A(x,y)=2x+y, :u_B(x,y)=x+2y. Note that the utilities are weakly-convex and strongly-monotone. Many PEEF allocations exist. If Alice receives at least 3 units of x, then her utility is 6 and she does not envy Bob. Similarly, if Bob receives at least 3 units of y, he does not envy Alice. So the allocation 3,0);(1,4)is PEEF with utilities (6,9). Similarly, the allocations 4,0);(0,4)and 4,0.5);(0,3.5)are PEEF. On the other hand, the allocation 0,0);(4,4)is PE but not EF (Alice envies Bob); the allocation 2,2);(2,2)is EF but not PE (the utilities are (6,6) but they can be improved e.g. to (8,8)). B. Essentially-single PEEF allocation: The total endowment is (4,2). Alice and Bob have
Leontief utilities In economics, especially in consumer theory, a Leontief utility function is a function of the form: u(x_1,\ldots,x_m)=\min\left\ . where: * m is the number of different goods in the economy. * x_i (for i\in 1,\dots,m) is the amount of good i in the ...
, representing complementary goods: :u_A(x,y)=u_B(x,y)=\min(x,y). Note that the utilities are weakly-convex and only weakly-monotone. Still A PEEF allocation exists. The equal allocation 2,1);(2,1)is PEEF with utility vector (1,1). EF is obvious (every equal allocation is EF). Regarding PE, note that both agents now want only y, so the only way to increase the utility of an agent is to take some y from the other agent, but this decreases the utility of the other agent. While there are other PEEF allocations, e.g. 1.5,1);(2.5,1) all have the same utility vector of (1,1), since it is not possible to give both agents more than 1.


Topological conditions on the space of efficient allocations

PEEF allocations exist even when agents' preferences are not convex. There are several sufficient conditions that are related to the shape of the set of allocations corresponding to a specific efficient utility profile. Given a utility-vector u, define A(u) = the set of all allocations for which the utility-profile is u. The following successively more general theorems were proved by different authors: ''Theorem 2 (Varian): Suppose all agents' preferences are strongly
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
. If, for every Weakly Pareto Efficient utility-profile u, the set A(u) is a singleton (i.e, there are no two WPE allocations such that all agents are indifferent between them), then PEEF allocations exist.'' The proof uses the
Knaster–Kuratowski–Mazurkiewicz lemma The Knaster–Kuratowski–Mazurkiewicz lemma is a basic result in mathematical fixed-point theory published in 1929 by Knaster, Kuratowski and Mazurkiewicz. The KKM lemma can be proved from Sperner's lemma and can be used to prove the Brouwer f ...
. ''Note'': The conditions in Theorem 1 and in Theorem 2 are independent - none of them implies the other. However, ''strict-convexity of preferences'' implies both of them. It is obvious that strict-convexity implies weak-convexity (theorem 1). To see that it implies the condition of theorem 2, suppose there are two different allocations x,y with the same utility profile u. Define z = x/2+y/2. By strict convexity, all agents strictly prefer z to x and to y. Hence, x and y cannot be weakly-PE. ''Theorem 3 (Svensson): If all agents' preferences are strongly
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
, and for every PE utility-profile u, the set A(u) is convex, then PEEF allocations exist.'' The proof uses the
Kakutani fixed-point theorem In mathematical analysis, the Kakutani fixed-point theorem is a fixed-point theorem for set-valued functions. It provides sufficient conditions for a set-valued function defined on a convex set, convex, compact set, compact subset of a Euclidean sp ...
. ''Note'': if all agents' preferences are convex (as in theorem 1), then A(u) is obviously convex too. Moreover, if A(u) is singleton (as in theorem 2) then it is obviously convex too. Hence, Svensson's theorem is more general than both Varian's theorems. ''Theorem 4 (Diamantaras): If all agents' preferences are strongly
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
, and for every PE utility-profile u, the set A(u) is a
contractible space In mathematics, a topological space ''X'' is contractible if the identity map on ''X'' is null-homotopic, i.e. if it is homotopic to some constant map. Intuitively, a contractible space is one that can be continuously shrunk to a point within that ...
(can be continuously shrunk to a point within that space), then PEEF allocations exist.'' The proof uses a fixed-point theorem by Eilenberg and Montgomery. ''Note:'' Every convex set is contractible, so Diamantaras' theorem is more general than the previous three.


Sigma-optimality

Svensson proved another sufficient condition for the existence of PEEF allocations. Again all preferences are represented by continuous utility functions. Moreover, all utility functions are continuously differentiable in the interior of the consumption space. The main concept is ''sigma-optimality''. Suppose we create, for each agent, k copies with identical preferences. Let ''X'' be an allocation in the original economy. Let ''Xk'' be an allocation in the k-replicated economy where all copies of the same agent receive the same bundle as the original agent in X. The allocation ''X'' is called ''sigma-optimal'' if for every ''k'', the allocation ''Xk'' is Pareto-optimal. ''Lemma: An allocation is sigma-optimal, if-and-only-if it is a
competitive equilibrium Competitive equilibrium (also called: Walrasian equilibrium) is a concept of economic equilibrium introduced by Kenneth Arrow and Gérard Debreu in 1951 appropriate for the analysis of commodity markets with flexible prices and many traders, and se ...
.'' ''Theorem 5 (Svensson):'' ''if all Pareto-optimal allocations are sigma-optimal, then PEEF allocations exist.''


Increasing marginal returns

PEEF allocations might fail to exist even when all preferences are convex, if there is production and the technology has increasing-marginal-returns. Proposition 6 (Vohra)'': T''here exist economies in which all preferences are continuous strongly-monotone and convex, the only source of non-convexity in the technology is due to fixed costs, and there exists no PEEF allocation. Thus, the presence of increasing returns introduces a fundamental conflict between efficiency and fairness. However, envy-freeness can be weakened in the following way. An allocation X is defined as ''essentially envy-free (EEF)'' if, for every agent ''i'', there is a feasible allocation ''Yi'' with the same utility profile (all agents are indifferent between X and Yi) in which agent i does not envy anyone. Obviously, every EF allocation is EEF, since we can take Yi to be X for all i. ''Theorem 7 (Vohra): Suppose all agents' preferences are strongly
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
, and represented by continuous utility functions. Then, Pareto-efficient EEF allocations exist.''


Non-existence of PEEF allocations


Non-convex preferences

PEEF allocations might fail to exist even without production, when the preferences are non-convex. As an example, suppose the total endowment is (4,2), and Alice and Bob have identical concave utilities: :u_A(x,y)=u_B(x,y)=\max(x,y). The equal allocation 2,1);(2,1)is EF with utility vector (2,2). Moreover, ''every'' EF allocation must give both agents equal utility (since they have the same utility function) and this utility can be at most 2. However, no such allocation is PE, since it is Pareto-dominated by the allocation 4,0);(0,2)whose utility vector is (4,2). Non-existence remains even if we weaken envy-freeness to ''no domination --'' no agent gets more of each good than another agent. ''Proposition 8 (Maniquet): There exist 2-good 3-agent division economies with strictly monotonic, continuous and even differentiable preferences, where there is domination at every Pareto efficient allocation.''


Finding a PEEF allocation

For two agents, the adjusted winner procedure is a simple procedure that finds a PEEF allocation with two additional properties: the allocation is also equitable, and at most a single good is shared between the two agents. For three or more agents with linear utilities, any ''Nash-optimal allocation'' is PEEF. A Nash-optimal allocation is an allocation that maximizes the ''product'' of the utilities of the agents, or equivalently, the sum of logarithms of utilities. Finding such an allocation is a
convex optimization Convex optimization is a subfield of mathematical optimization that studies the problem of minimizing convex functions over convex sets (or, equivalently, maximizing concave functions over convex sets). Many classes of convex optimization pr ...
problem: \text \sum_^n \log(u_i(X_i)) ~~~\text~~~ (X_1,\ldots,X_n) ~~~\text~~~. and thus it can be found efficiently. The fact that any Nash-optimal allocation is PEEF is true even in the more general setting of
fair cake-cutting Fair cake-cutting is a kind of fair division problem. The problem involves a ''heterogeneous'' resource, such as a cake with different toppings, that is assumed to be ''divisible'' – it is possible to cut arbitrarily small pieces of it without ...
. ''Proof'': Consider an infinitesimal piece of cake, ''Z''. For each agent ''i'', the infinitesimal contribution of ''Z'' to \log(u_i(X_i))is u_i(Z)\cdot = . Therefore, the Nash-optimal rule gives each such piece ''Z'' to an agent ''j'' for which this expression is largest:
\forall j\in Z\subseteq X_j \iff \forall i\in \geq Summing over all infinitesimal subsets of ''Xj'', we get: \forall i,j\in \geq This implies the definition of envy-free allocation: \forall i,j\in \geq


See also

*
Weller's theorem Weller's theorem is a theorem in economics. It says that a heterogeneous resource ("cake") can be divided among ''n'' partners with different valuations in a way that is both Pareto-efficient (PE) and envy-free (EF). Thus, it is possible to divide ...
- on the existence of PEEF allocations in cake-cutting. * More related theorems by
Hal Varian Hal Ronald Varian (born March 18, 1947 in Wooster, Ohio) is Chief Economist at Google and holds the title of emeritus professor at the University of California, Berkeley where he was founding dean of the School of Information. Varian is an eco ...
can be found in. * Theorems about PEEF allocations in economies with production can be found in. *
Market equilibrium computation Market equilibrium computation (also called competitive equilibrium computation or clearing-prices computation) is a computational problem in the intersection of economics and computer science. The input to this problem is a ''market'', consisting ...
- algorithms for computing a competitive equilibrium, which is both fair and efficient. *Tao and Cole study the existence of PEEF random allocations when the utilities are non-linear (can have complements). *Diamantaras and Thomson study a refinement and extension of envy-freeness, which exists (together with PE) in many economies in which a PEEF allocation does not exist.


References

{{reflist Fair division Economics theorems Pareto efficiency